Logic of Discovery or Psychology of Research? / Logik oder Psychologie der Forschung? (Englisch/Deutsch)

Tekst
0
Recenzje
Przeczytaj fragment
Oznacz jako przeczytane
Czcionka:Mniejsze АаWiększe Aa

II

With the background supplied by the preceding remarks we can quickly discover the occasion and consequences of another of Sir Karl’s favourite locutions. The preface to Conjectures and Refutations opens with the sentence: ‘The essays and lectures of which this book is composed, are variations upon one very simple theme – the thesis that we can learn from our mistakes.’ The emphasis is Sir Karl’s; the [48]thesis recurs in his writing from an early date26; taken in isolation, it inevitably commands assent. Everyone [11] can and does learn from his mistakes; isolating and correcting them is an essential technique in teaching children. Sir Karl’s rhetoric has roots in everyday experience. Nevertheless, in the contexts for which he invokes this familiar imperative, its applications seems decisively askew. I am not sure a mistake has been made, at least not a mistake to learn from.

One need not confront the deeper philosophical problems presented by mistakes to see what is presently at issue. It is a mistake to add three plus three and get five, or to conclude from ‘All men are mortal’ to ‘All mortals are men’. For different reasons, it is a mistake to say, ‘He is my sister’, or to report the presence of a strong electric field when test charges fail to indicate it. Presumably there are still other sorts of mistakes, but all the normal ones are likely to share the following characteristics. A mistake is made, or is [50]committed, at a specifiable time and place by a particular individual. That individual has failed to obey some established rule of logic, or of language, or of the relations between one of these and experience. Or he may instead have failed to recognize the consequences of a particular choice among the alternatives which the rules allow him. The individual can learn from his mistake only because the group whose practice embodies these rules can isolate the individual’s failure in applying them. In short, the sorts of mistakes to which Sir Karl’s imperative most obviously applies are in individual’s failure of understanding or of recognition within an activity governed by pre-established rules. In the sciences such mistakes occur most frequently and perhaps exclusively within the practice of normal puzzle-solving research.

That is not, however, where Sir Karl seeks them, for his concept of science obscures even the existence of normal research. Instead, he looks to the extraordinary or revolutionary episodes in scientific development. The mistakes to which he points are not usually acts at all but rather out-of-date scientific theories: Ptolemaic astronomy, the phlogiston theory, or Newtonian dynamics, and ‘learning from our mistakes’ is, correspondingly, what occurs when a scientific community rejects one of these theories and replaces it with another.27 If this does not immediately seem an [52]odd usage, [12] that is mainly because it appeals to the residual inductivist in us all. Believing that valid theories are the product of correct inductions from facts, the inductivist must also hold that a false theory is the result of a mistake in induction. In principle, at least, he is prepared to answer the questions: what mistake was made, what rule broken, when and by whom, in arriving at, say, the Ptolemaic system? To the man for whom those are sensible questions and to him alone, Sir Karl’s locution presents no problems.

But neither Sir Karl nor I is an inductivist. We do not believe that there are rules for inducing correct theories from [54]facts, or even that theories, correct or incorrect, are induced at all. Instead we view them as imaginative posits, invented in one piece for application to nature. And though we point out that such posits can and usually do at last encounter puzzles they cannot solve, we also recognize that those troublesome confrontations rarely occur for some time after a theory has been both invented and accepted. In our view, then, no mistake was made in arriving at the Ptolemaic system, and it is therefore difficult for me to understand what Sir Karl has in mind when he calls that system, or any other out-of-date theory, a mistake. At most one may wish to say that a theory which was not previously a mistake has become one or that a scientist has made the mistake of clinging to a theory for too long. And even these locutions, of which at least the first is extremely awkward, do not return us to the sense of mistake with which we are most familiar. Those mistakes are the normal ones which a Ptolemaic (or a Copernican) astronomer makes within his system, perhaps in observation, calculation, or the analysis of data. They are, that is, the sort of mistake which can be isolated and then at once corrected, leaving the original system intact. In Sir Karl’s sense, on the other hand, a mistake infects an entire system and can be corrected only by [56]replacing the system as a whole. No locutions and no similarities can disguise these fundamental differences, nor can it hide the fact that before infection set in the system had the full integrity of what we now call sound knowledge.

Quite possibly Sir Karl’s sense of ‘mistake’ can be salvaged, but a successful salvage operation must deprive it of certain still current implications. Like the term ‘testing’, ‘mistake’ has been borrowed from normal science, where its use is reasonably clear, and applied to revolutionary episodes, where its application is at best problematic. That transfer creates, or at least reinforces, the prevalent impression that whole theories can be judged by the same sort of criteria that one employs when judging a theory’s individual research applications. The discovery of applicable criteria then becomes a primary desideratum for many people. That Sir [13] Karl should be among them is strange, for the search runs counter to the most original and fruitful thrust in his philosophy of science. But I can understand his methodological writings since the Logik der Forschung in no other way. I shall now suggest that he has, despite explicit disclaimers, consistently sought evaluation procedures which can be applied to theories with the apodictic assurance characteristic of the techniques by which one identifies mistakes in arithmetic, logic, or measurement. I fear that he is pursuing a will-o’-the-wisp born from the same conjunction[58] of normal and extraordinary science which made tests seem so fundamental a feature of the sciences.

III

In his Logik der Forschung, Sir Karl underlined the asymmetry of a generalization and its negation in their relation to empirical evidence. A scientific theory cannot be shown to apply successfully to all its possible instances, but it can be shown to be unsuccessful in particular applications. Emphasis upon that logical truism and its implications seems to me a forward step from which there must be no retreat. The same asymmetry plays a fundamental role in my Structure of Scientific Revolutions, where a theory’s failure to provide rules that identify solvable puzzles is viewed as the source of professional crises which often result in the theory’s being replaced. My point is very close to Sir Karl’s, and I may well have taken it from what I had heard of his work.

But Sir Karl describes as ‘falsification’ or ‘refutation’ what happens when a theory fails in an attempted application, and these are the first of a series of related locutions that again strike me as extremely odd. Both ‘falsification’ and ‘refutation’ are antonyms of ‘proof’. They are drawn principally from logic and from formal mathematics; the chains [60]of argument to which they apply end with a ‘Q.E.D.’; invoking these terms implies the ability to compel assent from any member of the relevant professional community. No member of this audience, however, still needs to be told that, where a whole theory or often even a scientific law is at stake, arguments are seldom so apodictic. All experiments can be challenged, either as to their relevance or their accuracy. All theories can be modified by a variety of ad hoc adjustments without ceasing to be, in their main lines, the same theories. It is important, furthermore, that this should be so, for it is often by challenging observations or adjusting theories that scientific knowledge grows. Challenges and adjustments are a standard part of normal research in empirical science, and adjustments, at least, play a dominant role in informal mathematics as well. Dr Lakatos’s brilliant analysis of the permissible rejoinders to mathematical refutations [14] provides the most telling arguments I know against a naive falsificationist position.28

Sir Karl is not, of course, a naive falsificationist. He knows all that has just been said and has emphasized it from the beginning of his career. Very early in his Logic of Scientific Discovery, for example, he writes: ‘In point of fact, no conclusive disproof of a theory can ever be [62]produced; for it is always possible to say that the experimental results are not reliable or that the discrepancies which are asserted to exist between the experimental results and the theory are only apparent and that they will disappear with the advance of our understanding.’29 Statements like these display one more parallel between Sir Karl’s view of science and my own, but what we make of them could scarcely be more different. For my view they are fundamental, both as evidence and as source. For Sir Karl’s, in contrast, they are an essential qualification which threatens the integrity of his basic position. Having barred conclusive disproof, he has provided no substitute for it, and the relation he does employ remains that of logical falsification. Though he is not a naive falsificationist, Sir Karl may, I suggest, legitimately be treated as one.

 

If his concern were exclusively with demarcation, the problems posed by the unavailability of conclusive disproofs would be less severe and perhaps eliminable. Demarcation might, that is, be achieved by an exclusively syntactic criterion.30 Sir Karl’s view would then be, and perhaps is, that a theory is scientific if and only if observation [64]statements – particularly the negations of singular existential statements – can be logically deduced from it, perhaps in conjunction with stated background knowledge. The difficulties (to which I shall shortly turn) in deciding whether the outcome of a particular laboratory operation justifies asserting a particular observation statement would then be irrelevant. Perhaps, though the basis for doing so is less apparent, the equally grave difficulties in deciding whether an observation statement deduced from an approximate (e.g. mathematically manageable) version of the theory should be considered consequences of the theory itself could be eliminated in the same way. Problems like these would belong not to the syntactics but to the pragmatics or semantics of the language in which the theory was cast, and they would therefore have no role in determining its status as a science. To be scientific a theory need be falsifiable only by an observation statement not by actual observation. The relation between statements, unlike that between [15] a statement and an observation, could be the conclusive disproof familiar from logic and mathematics.

For reasons suggested above (p. 9, footnote 1) and elaborated immediately below, I doubt that scientific theories can without decisive change be cast in a form which permits the purely syntactic judgements which this version of Sir Karl’s criterion requires. But even if they could, these [66]reconstructed theories would provide a basis only for his demarcation criterion, not for the logic of knowledge so closely associated with it. The latter has, however, been Sir Karl’s most persistent concern, and his notion of it is quite precise. ‘The logic of knowledge …,’ he writes, ‘consists solely in investigating the methods employed in those systematic tests to which every new idea must be subjected if it is to be seriously entertained!’31 From this investigation, he continues, result methodological rules or conventions like the following: ‘Once a hypothesis has been proposed and tested, and has proved its mettle, it may not be allowed to drop out without “good reason”. A “good reason” may be, for instance … the falsification of one of the consequences of the hypothesis.’32

Rules like these, and with them the entire logical enterprise described above, are no longer simply syntactic in their import. They require that both the epistemological investigator and the research scientist be able to relate sentences derived from a theory not to other sentences but to actual observations and experiments. This is the context in which Sir Karl’s term ‘falsification’ must function, and Sir Karl is entirely silent about how it can do so. What is falsification if it is not conclusive disproof? Under what circumstances does the logic of knowledge require a scientist to abandon a previously accepted theory when confronted, [68]not with statements about experiments, but with experiments themselves? Pending clarification of these questions, I am not clear that what Sir Karl has given us is a logic of knowledge at all. In my conclusion I shall suggest that, though equally valuable, it is something else entirely. Rather than a logic, Sir Karl has provided an ideology; rather than methodological rules, he has supplied procedural maxims.

That conclusion must, however, be postponed until after a last deeper look at the source of the difficulties with Sir Karl’s notion of falsification. It presupposes, as I have already suggested, that a theory is cast, or can without distortion be recast, in a form which permits scientists to classify each conceivable event as either a confirming instance, a falsifying instance, or irrelevant to the theory. That is obviously required if a general law is to be falsifiable: to test the generalization (x) φ (x) by applying it to the constant a, we must be able to tell whether or not a lies within the [16] range of the variable x and whether or not φ (a). The same presupposition is even more apparent in Sir Karl’s recently elaborated measure of verisimilitude. It requires that we first produce the class of all logical consequences of the theory and then choose from among these, with the aid of background knowledge, the classes of all true and of all false consequences.33 At least, we must do this if the criterion of [70]verisimilitude is to result in a method of theory choice. None of these tasks can, however, be accomplished unless the theory is fully articulated logically and unless the terms through which it attaches to nature are sufficiently defined to determine their applicability in each possible case. In practice, however, no scientific theory satisfies these rigorous demands, and many people have argued that a theory would cease to be useful in research if it did so.34 I have myself elsewhere introduced the term ‘paradigm’ to underscore the dependence of scientific research upon concrete examples that bridge what would otherwise be gaps in the specification of the content and application of scientific theories. The relevant arguments cannot be repeated here. But a brief example, though it will temporarily alter my mode of discourse, may be even more useful.

My example takes the form of a constructed epitome of some elementary scientific knowledge. That knowledge concerns swans, and to isolate its presently relevant [72]characteristics I shall ask three questions about it: (a) How much can one know about swans without introducing explicit generalizations like ‘All swans are white’? (b) Under what circumstances and with what consequences are such generalizations worth adding to what was known without them? (c) Under what circumstances are generalizations rejected once they have been made? In raising these questions my object is to suggest that, though logic is a powerful and ultimately an essential tool of scientific enquiry, one can have sound knowledge in forms to which logic can scarcely be applied. Simultaneously, I shall suggest that logical articulation is not a value for its own sake, but is to be undertaken only when and to the extent that circumstances demand it.

Imagine that you have been shown and can remember ten birds which have authoritatively been identified as swans; that you have a similar acquaintance with ducks, geese, pigeons, doves, gulls, etc.; and that you are informed that each of these types constitutes a natural family. A natural family you already know as an observed cluster of like objects, [17] sufficiently important and sufficiently discrete to command a generic name. More precisely, though here I introduce more simplification than the concept requires, a natural family is a class whose members resemble each other more closely than they resemble the members of other natural families.35 The experience of generations has to [74]date confirmed that all observed objects fall into one or another natural family. It has, that is, shown that the entire population of the world can always be divided (though not once and for all) into perceptually discontinuous categories. In the perceptual spaces between these categories there are believed to be no objects at all.

What you have learned about swans from exposure to paradigms is yery much like what children first learn about dogs and cats, tables and chairs, mothers and fathers. Its precise scope and content are, of course, impossible to specify, but it is sound knowledge nonetheless. Derived from observation, it can be infirmed by further observation, and it meanwhile provides a basis for rational action. Seeing a bird much like the swans you already know, you may reasonably presume that it will require the same food as the others and will breed with them. Provided swans are a natural family, no bird which closely resembles them on sight should display radically different characteristics on [76]closer acquaintance. Of course you may have been misinformed about the natural integrity of the swan family. But that can be discovered from experience, for example, by the discovery of a number of animals (note that more than one is required) whose characteristics bridge the gap between swans and, say, geese by barely perceptible intervals.36 Until that does occur, however, you will know a great deal about swans though you will not be altogether sure what you know or what a swan is.

Suppose now that all the swans you have actually observed are white. Should you embrace the generalization, ‘All swans are white’? Doing so will change what you know very little; that change will be of use only in the unlikely event that you meet a non-white bird which otherwise resembles a swan; by making the change you increase the risk that the swan [18] family will prove not to be a natural family after all. Under those circumstances you are likely to refrain from generalizing unless there are special reasons for doing so. Perhaps, for example, you must describe swans to men who cannot be directly exposed to paradigms. [78]Without superhuman caution both on your part and on that of your readers, your description will acquire the force of a generalization; this is often the problem of the taxonomist. Or perhaps you have discovered some grey birds that look otherwise like swans but eat different food and have an unfortunate disposition. You may then generalize to avoid a behavioural mistake. Or you may have a more theoretical reason for thinking the generalization worthwhile. For example, you may have observed that the members of other natural families share colouration. Specifying this fact in a form which permits the application of powerful logical techniques to what you know may enable you to learn more about the animal colour in general or about animal breeding.

Now, having made the generalization, what will you do if you encounter a black bird that looks otherwise like a swan? Almost the same things, I suggest, as if you had not previously committed yourself to the generalization at all. You will examine the bird with care, externally and perhaps internally as well, to find other characteristics that distinguish this specimen from your paradigms. That examination will be particularly long and thorough if you have theoretical reasons for believing that colour characterizes natural families or if you are deeply ego involved with the generalization. Very likely the examination will disclose other differentiae, and you will announce the discovery of a [80]new natural family. Or you may fail to find such differentiae and may then announce that a black swan has been found. Observation cannot, however, force you to that falsifying conclusion, and you would occasionally be the loser if it could do so. Theoretical considerations may suggest that colour alone is sufficient to demarcate a natural family: the bird is not a swan because it is black. Or you may simply postpone the issue pending the discovery and examination of other specimens. Only if you have previously committed yourself to a full definition of ‘swan’, one which will specify its applicability to every conceivable object, can you be logically forced to rescind your generalization.37 And why should you have offered such a definition? It could serve no cognitive function and would [19] expose you to [82]tremendous risks.38 Risks, of course, are often worth taking, but to say more than one knows solely for the sake of risk is foolhardy.

I suggest that scientific knowledge, though logically more articulate and far more complex, is of this sort. The books and teachers from whom it is acquired present concrete examples together with a multitude of theoretical generalizations. Both are essential carriers of knowledge, and it is therefore Pickwickian to seek a methodological criterion that supposes the scientist can specify in advance whether each imaginable instance fits or would falsify his theory. The criteria at his disposal, explicit and implicit, are sufficient to answer that question only for the cases that clearly do fit or that are clearly irrelevant. These are the cases he expects, the ones for which his knowledge was designed. Confronted with the unexpected, he must always do more research in order further to articulate his theory in the area that has just become problematic. He may then reject it in favour of another and for good reason. But no exclusively logical criteria can entirely dictate the conclusion he must draw.

 
To koniec darmowego fragmentu. Czy chcesz czytać dalej?