Za darmo

History of Modern Philosophy

Tekst
iOSAndroidWindows Phone
Gdzie wysłać link do aplikacji?
Nie zamykaj tego okna, dopóki nie wprowadzisz kodu na urządzeniu mobilnym
Ponów próbęLink został wysłany

Na prośbę właściciela praw autorskich ta książka nie jest dostępna do pobrania jako plik.

Można ją jednak przeczytać w naszych aplikacjach mobilnych (nawet bez połączenia z internetem) oraz online w witrynie LitRes.

Oznacz jako przeczytane
Czcionka:Mniejsze АаWiększe Aa

In morals Mill may be considered the creator of what Henry Sidgwick, in his Methods of Ethics (1874), called Universalistic Hedonism. The English moralists of the eighteenth century had set up the greatest happiness of the greatest number as the ideal end of action; but they did not hold that each individual could be expected to pursue anything but his own happiness; the object of Bentham (1748-1832) being to make the two coincide. Kant showed that the rule of right excluded any such accommodation, and a crisis in his own life led Mill to adopt the same conclusion. Afterwards he rather confused the issues by distinguishing between higher and lower pleasures, leaving experts to decide which were the pleasures to be preferred. The universalistic standard settles the question summarily by estimating pleasures according to their social utility.

Mill fully sympathised with Comte's demand for social reorganisation as a means towards the moral end. But, with his English and Protestant traditions, he had no faith in the creation of a new spiritual power with an elaborate religious code and ritual as the best machinery for the purpose. In his opinion, the claims of the individual to extended liberty of thought and action, not their restriction, were what first needed attention. Second to this – if second at all – came the necessity for reforming representative government on the lines of an enlarged franchise and a readjusted electoral system with plural suffrage determined by merit, votes for women, and a contrivance for giving minorities a weight proportioned to their numbers. The problem of poverty was to be dealt with by restrictions on the increase of population and on the amount of inheritable property, the maximum of which ought not to exceed a modest competence.

Among the noble characters presented by the history of philosophy we may distinguish between the heroic and the saintly types. To the former in modern times belong Giordano Bruno, Fichte, and to some extent Comte; to the latter, Spinoza, Berkeley, and Kant. To the second class we may surely add John Stuart Mill, whom Gladstone called "the saint of rationalism," and of whom Auguste Laugel said, "He was not sincere – he was sincerity itself."

Herbert Spencer

Herbert Spencer (1820-1903) was the son of a Nonconformist country schoolmaster, but was educated chiefly by his uncle Thomas, an Evangelical clergyman of the Church of England. A radical reformer of the old school, Thomas Spencer seems to have indoctrinated his youthful charge with the germinal principles afterwards generalised into a whole cosmic philosophy. He had a passion for justice realised under the form of liberty, individual responsibility, and self-help. In his opinion, until it was modified by private misfortunes, everything served everybody right. Beginning as an economical administrator of the new Poor Law, he at last became an advocate of its total abolition; and, alone among fifteen thousand clergymen, he was an active member of the Anti-Corn Law League, besides supporting the separation of Church and State. At twenty-two Herbert Spencer accepted and summed up this policy under the form of a general hostility to State interference with individual liberty, supporting it by a reference to the reign of Natural Law in all orders of existence. In his first great work, Social Statics, the principle of laissez-faire received its full systematic development as the restriction of State action to the defence of liberty against internal and external aggression, the raising of taxes for any other purpose being unjust, as is also private ownership of land, which is by nature the common heritage of all. Spencer subsequently came to abandon land nationalisation, probably from alarm at its socialistic implications.

The doctrine of natural law and liberty carried with it for Spencer a strong repugnance not only to protectionism in politics, but also to miracles in theology. The profession of journalism brought him into touch with a freethinking set in London. Whether under their influence, or Shelley's, or by some spontaneous process, his religious convictions evaporated by twenty-eight into the agnosticism which thenceforth remained their permanent expression. There might or not be a First Cause; if there was, we know nothing about it. At this stage Lyell's attempted refutation of Lamarck converted Spencer to the belief in man's derivation from some lower animal by a process of gradual adaptation. Thus the scion of an educationalist family came to interpret the whole history of life on our planet as an educative process.

It seemed, however, as if there was one fatal exception to the scheme of naturalistic optimism. The Rev. Thomas Malthus had originally published his Essay on Population (1798) as a telling answer to the "infidel" Godwin's Political Justice (1793), the bolder precursor of Social Statics. The argument was that the tendency of population to outrun the means of subsistence put human perfectibility out of the question. It had been suggested by the idealists, Mill among the number, that the difficulty might be obviated by habitual self-restraint on the part of married people. But Spencer, with great ingenuity, made the difficulty its own solution. The pressure of population on the means of subsistence is the source of all progress; and of progress not only in discoveries and inventions, but also, through its increased exercise, in the instrument which effects them – that is, the human brain. Now, it is a principle of Aristotle's, revived by modern biology, that individuation is antagonistic to reproduction; and increasing individuation is the very law of developing life, shown above all in the growing power of life's chief instrument, which is thought's organ, the brain. For, as Spencer proceeded to show in his next work, the Principles of Psychology, life means a continuous series of adjustments of internal to external relations. Therefore the rate of multiplication must go on falling with the growth of intellectual and moral power until it only just suffices to balance the loss by death. The next step was to revive Laplace's nebular hypothesis, and to connect it through Lyell's uniformitarian geology with Lamarck's developmental biology, thereby extending the same evolutionary process through the whole history of the universe.

Nor was this all. Milne-Edwards, by another return to Aristotle, had pointed to the "physiological division of labour" as a mark of ascending organic perfection, to which Spencer adds integration of structure as its obverse side, at the same time extending the world-law, already made familiar in part through its industrial applications by Adam Smith, to all orders of social activity. Finally, differentiation and integration were stretched back from living to lifeless matter, thus bringing astronomy and geology, which had already entered into the causal series of cosmic transformations, under one common law of evolution; while at the same time, seeing it to be generally admitted that inorganic changes originated from the operation of purely mechanical forces, they suggested that mechanism, without teleology, could adequately explain organic evolution also.

Finally came the great discovery of Darwin and Wallace, with its extension of Malthus's law to the whole world of living things. Spencer had just touched, without grasping, the same idea years before. He now gladly accepted Natural Selection as supplementing without superseding Lamarck's theory of spontaneous adaptation.

To complete even in outline the vast sweep of his projected Synthetic Philosophy two steps more remained for Spencer to take. The law of evolution had to be brought under the recently-discovered law of the Conservation of Energy, or, as he called it, the Persistence of Force, and the whole of unified science had to be reconciled with religion. The first problem was solved by interpreting evolution as a redistribution of matter and motion – a process in which, of course, energy is neither lost nor gained. The second problem was solved by reducing faith and knowledge to the common denominator of Agnosticism – a method that found more favour with Positivists (in the wide sense) than with Christian believers.

Herbert Spencer was disappointed to find that people took more interest in the portico (as he called it in a letter to the present writer) – that is to say, the metaphysical introduction to his philosophical edifice – than in its interior. He probably had some suspicion that the portico was mere lath and plaster, while he felt sure that the columns and architraves behind it were of granite. The public, however, besides their perennial interest in religion, might be excused for giving more attention to even a baroque exterior with some novelty about it than to the formalised eclecticism of what stood behind it. Unfortunately, they soon found that the alleged reconciliation was a palpable sham. Religion is nothing if not a revelation, and an unknowable God is no God at all. Even the pretended proofs of that poor residual deity involved their author in the transparent self-contradiction of calling the universe the manifestation of an Unknowable Power. Then the relations between this Power (such as it was) and the Energy (or Force) whose conservation (or persistence) was the very first of First Principles seemed hard to adjust. Either energy is created, or it is not. In the one case, what becomes of its eternity? in the other case, what need is there to assume a Power (knowable or not) behind it? Science will not shrink back before such a phantom, nor will Religion adore it.

Such faulty building in the portico prepares us for somewhat unsteady masonry within; and in fact none holds together except what has been transported bodily from other temples. In the past history of the universe, considered as a "rearrangement of matter and motion," disintegration and assimilation play quite as great a part as integration and differentiation. Such formulas have no advantage over the metaphysical systematisation of Aristotle, and they give us as little power either to predict or to direct. Will war be abolished at some future time, or property equalised or abolished, or morality exalted, or religion superseded? Spencer was ready with his answer; but the law of evolution could not prove it true. Nevertheless, his name will long be associated with evolution as a world-wide process, though neither in the way of original discovery nor of complete generalisation, and far less of successful application to modern problems; but rather of diffusion and popularisation, even as other valuable ideas have been impressed on the public mind by other philosophies at a vast expense of ingenuity, knowledge, and labour, but not at greater expense than the eventual gain has been worth.

 
The English Hegelians

Hegel's philosophy first drew attention in England through its supposed connection with Strauss's mythic theory of the Gospels and Baur's theory of New Testament literature as a product of party conflicts and compromises in the primitive Church. Rightly interpreted as a system of Pantheism, it was decried and ridiculed by orthodox theologians in the name of religion and common sense, while cherished by the advanced Broad Church as a means of symbolising away the creeds they continued to repeat. Then the triumph of Spencer's Agnosticism in the middle Victorian period (1864-1874) suggested an appeal to a logic whose object had been to resolve the negations of eighteenth-century enlightenment in the synthesis of a higher unity. The first pronunciation in this sense was The Secret of Hegel (1865), by Dr. Hutchison Stirling (1820-1909), a writer of geniality and genius, who, writing from the Hegelian standpoint, tried to represent the English rationalists of the day as a superficial and retrograde school. It was a bold but unsuccessful attempt to plant the banner of the Hegelian Right on British soil. By attacking Darwinism Stirling put himself out of touch with the general movement of thought. Professor William Wallace (1844-1897), John Caird (1820-1898), and his brother Edward Caird (1835-1908) inclined more or less to the Left, as also does Lord Haldane (b. 1865) in his Gifford Lectures (1903); and all have the advantage over Stirling of writing in a clearer if less picturesque style.

T. H. Green (1836-1882) is sometimes quoted as a Hegelian, but his intellectual affinities were rather with Fichte. According to him, reality is the thought of an Eternal Consciousness, of which personality need not be predicated, while the endless duration of personal spirits seems to be denied. Another idealist, F. H. Bradley (b. 1846) – perhaps the greatest living English thinker – develops in his Appearance and Reality (1893) a metaphysical system which, though Absolutist in form, is, to me at least, in substance practically indistinguishable from the dogmatic Agnosticism of Herbert Spencer, and even more destructive of the popular Theism. Finally the writings of Dr. J. E. McTaggart (b. 1866), teaching as they do a doctrine of developmental personal immortality without a God, show a tendency to combine Hegel with Lotze.

The German Eclectics

By general consent the most serious and influential of German systematic thinkers since Hegel is R. H. Lotze (1817-1881). His philosophy is built up of materials derived in varying proportions from all his German predecessors, the most distinctive idea being pluralism, probably suggested in the first instance by Herbart, whom he succeeded as Professor at Göttingen. But Lotze discards the rigid monads of his master for the more intelligible soul-substances of Leibniz – or rather of Bruno – whose example he also follows in his attempt to combine pluralism with monism. Very strenuous efforts are made to give the unifying principle the character of a personal God; but the suspicion of a leaning to Pantheism is not altogether eluded.

More original and far more uncompromising is the work of Ed. v. Hartmann (1842-1906). Personally he enjoyed the twofold distinction – whatever it may be worth – of having served as an officer for a short time in the Prussian army, and of never having taught in a university. His great work, published at twenty-seven, appeared under the telling title of the Philosophy of the Unconscious. It won immediate popularity, and reached its eleventh edition in 1904. Hartmann adopts, with some slight attenuation, Schopenhauer's pessimism, and his metaphysics with a considerable emendation. In this new version the world is still conceived as Will and Representation; but whereas for Schopenhauer the intellective side had been subordinated to the volitional, with Hartmann the two are co-equal and intimately united, together forming that "Unconscious" which is the new Absolute. In this way Reason again becomes, what it had been with Hegel, a great cosmic principle; only as the optimistic universe had argued itself into existence, so conversely the pessimistic universe has to argue itself out of existence. As in the process of developing differentiation, the volitional and intellective sides draw apart, the Unconscious becomes self-conscious, and thus awakens to the terrible mistake it committed in willing to be. Thenceforth the whole of evolution is determined by the master-thought of how not to be. The problem is how to annul the creative Will. And the solution is to divide it into two halves so opposed that the one shall be the negation and destruction of the other. There will be then, not indeed a certainty, but an equal chance of definitive self-annihilation and eternal repose. Thus, the immediate duty for mankind, as also their predestined task, is the furtherance of scientific and industrial progress as a means towards this consummation, which is likewise their predestined end. A religious colouring is given to the process by representing it as an inverted Christian scheme in which man figures as the redeemer of God —i. e. the Absolute – from the unspeakable torments to which he is now condemned by the impossibility of satisfying his will.

Like Hartmann, Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900), the greatest writer of modern Germany, took his start from Schopenhauer, but broke with pessimism at an early date, having come to disbelieve in the hedonism on which it is founded. His restless vanity drove him to improve on Darwinism by interpreting evolution as the means towards creating what he called the Superman – that is, a race as much superior to us as we are to the apes. Progress, however, is not to be in the direction of a higher morality, but of greater power – the Will-to-Power, not the Will-to-Live, being the essence of what is. Later in life Nietzsche revived the Stoic doctrine that events move, and have moved through all time, in a series of recurring cycles, each being the exact repetition of its predecessor. It is a worthless idea, and Nietzsche, who had been a Greek professor, must have known where he got it; but the megalomania to which he eventually succumbed prevented his recognising the debt. By a merited irony of fate this worshipper of the Napoleonic type will survive only as a literary moralist in the history of thought.

The modern revolt against metaphysical systemisation, with or without a theological colouring, took in Germany the form of two distinct philosophical currents. The first is scientific materialism, or, as some of its advocates prefer to call it, energism. This began about 1850, but boasts two great living representatives, the biologist Haeckel and the chemist Ostwald. In their practical aims these men are idealists; but their admission of space and time as objective realities beyond which there is nothing, and their repudiation of agnosticism, distinguish them from the French and English Positivists. The other and more powerful school is known as Neo-Kantianism. It numbers numerous adherents in the German universities, and also in those of France and Italy, representing various shades of opinion united by a common reference to Kant's first Critique, dissociated from its concessions to deism, as the true starting-point of modern thought.

The Latest Developments

Since the beginning of the twentieth century the interest in philosophy and the ability devoted to its cultivation have shown no sign of diminution. Two new doctrines in particular have become subjects of world-wide discussion. I refer to the theory of knowledge called Pragmatism, and to the metaphysics of Professor Henri Bergson. Both are of so revolutionary, so contentious, and so elusive a character as to preclude any discussion or even outline of the new solutions for old problems which they claim to provide. But I would recommend the study of both, and especially of Bergson, to all who imagine that the possibilities of speculation are exhausted, or that we are any nearer finality and agreement than when Heracleitus first glorified war as the father of all things, and contradiction as the central spring of life.

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Kuno Fischer. Geschichte der neuern Philosophie. Nine vols. Fourth ed.; Heidelberg, 1897-1904. (Comes down to Schopenhauer.)

Erdmann. Geschichte der Philosophie. Vol. ii. Fourth ed.; Berlin, 1896. (Comes down to Lotze; third ed.; trans. by W. S. Hough; London, 1889.)

Windelband. Geschichte der neuern Philosophie. Two vols. Fifth ed. (Comes down to Herbart and Beneke. There is an English trans. of Windelband's General History of Philosophy, by J. H. Tufts, New York, 1893. In his contribution to the General History of Philosophy in the Kultur der Gegenwart, Berlin, 1909, Windelband includes a brief but useful summary of Pragmatism and Bergson.)

Levy-Bruhl. History of Modern Philosophy in France. Trans. by Miss Coblence. London, 1890.

Forsyth, T. M. English Philosophy: A Study of its Methods and General Development. London, 1910. (A. & C. Black.)

Giordano Bruno. Opere Italiane. Ed. P. Lagarde. Göttingen, 1888.

– Opera latine conscripta. Naples and Florence, 1879-91.

McIntyre, J. L. Life of Giordano Bruno. London, 1903.

Bacon, Francis. Works and Life. Ed. by Ellis and Spedding. Fourteen vols. 1864-74. – Works. One vol. Ed. by Ellis, Spedding, and Robertson. (Routledge.) —Novum Organum. Ed. by T. Fowler. Oxford, 1878.

Abbott, Edwin. Francis Bacon. London, 1885.

Church, R. W. Bacon (English Men of Letters). London, 1889.

Hobbes, Thomas. Works English and Latin. Ed. Sir Wm. Molesworth. Sixteen vols. London, 1839-45.

Robertson, G. C. Hobbes. London, 1886 (Blackwood's Philosophical Classics).

Stephen, Sir Leslie. Hobbes. London, 1903 (English Men of Letters).

– English Thought in the Eighteenth Century. Second ed.; two vols. London, 1881.

– The English Utilitarians. Three vols. London, 1900.

Descartes. Œuvres. Ed. V. Cousin. Eleven vols. Paris, 1824-1828. A new edition is in course of publication. – English trans. of the Method and the Meditations in the Scott Library. London, 1901. —Life, by Elizabeth Haldane. London, 1905.

Malebranche. Œuvres. Three vols. Ed. Jules Simon. Paris, 1871.

Spinoza. Opera. Ed. Van Vloten and Land. Two vols. The Hague, 1882-83.

– Life and Philosophy. By Sir Fr. Pollock. London, 1880; second ed., 1899.

– A Study of. By James Martineau. London, 1883.

's Ethics, A Study of. By H. H. Joachim. Oxford, 1901.

– Trans. of his principal works. By Elwes in Bohn's Library. Two vols., 1883-86. Also Everyman's Library. (Dent.)

– Ethics. Trans. by Hale White, revised by Amelia Stirling. London, 1899.

– Leben und Lehre. Von J. Frendenthal. 1904.

Leibniz. Philosophische Schriften. Seven vols. Ed. C. J. Gerhardt. Berlin, 1875-90. —The Philosophy of Leibniz. By Bertrand Russell. Cambridge, 1900.

Locke, John. Works. Nine vols. London, 1824.

– Essay Concerning Human Understanding. Two vols.; in Bohn's Library. London, 1877.

– Life of. By Fox Bourne. Two vols. London, 1876.

– By Thomas Fowler. London, 1880 (English Men of Letters).

– By Prof. A. C. Fraser; in Blackwood's Phil. Classics. 1890.

Berkeley, George. Works and Life. Ed. A. C. Fraser. Four vols. Oxford, 1871.

 

– By Fraser (Philosophical Classics). 1881.

Hume, David. Philosophical Works. Four vols. Ed. Green and Grose. London, 1874-75.

– By T. H. Huxley (English Men of Letters). New edition. London, 1894.

Kant. Werke. Ed. Rosenkranz and Schubert. Twelve vols. 1838-40. Two new editions, including the correspondence, are now in course of publication at Berlin. There are English translations of all the principal works.

– Life and Doctrine. By F. Paulsen; trans. by Creighton and Lefevre. London, 1908.

Fichte, J. G. Werke. Eleven vols. 1834-46. Trans. of his more popular works by Dr. W. Smith. Two vols. London, 1890.

Adamson. Fichte. In Blackwood's Phil. Classics. 1901.

Schelling, F. W. J. Werke. Fourteen vols. Stuttgart, 1856-61.

Watson, Prof. J. Schelling's Transcendental Idealism, Chicago, 1882.

Hegel, G. W. F. Werke. Nineteen vols. in twenty-one. Leipzig, 1832-87.

Hegel. By Prof. E. Caird (Philosophical Classics for English Readers.) Edinburgh, 1883. Hegel's Philosophies of Law, Religion, History, Mind, his History of Philosophy, and the smaller Logic, have been translated into English.

Schopenhauer. Werke. Six volumes in the Reclam Series. Leipzig, 1892.

Ribot. La Philosophie de Schopenhauer. Ninth ed.; Paris, 1909.

Wallace, Prof. W. Life of Schopenhauer (Great Writers Series). London, 1890.

Whittaker, Thomas. "Schopenhauer," in Philosophies Ancient and Modern. London, 1908.

Schopenhauer's World as Will and Idea. Trans. by Haldane and Kemp. Three vols. London, 1884-86. – Essays. Trans. by Belfort Bax (Bohn's Library). London, 1891.

Schopenhauer. Studies. Consisting of translations by T. Bailey Saunders. Seven vols. London, 1889-96. – Other essays translated by Madame Hillebrand (London, 1889) and by A. B. Ballock (London, 1903)

Herbart, J. F. Werke. Ed. Kehrbach. Fifteen vols. 1887 ff.

Wagner. Vollständige Darstellung d. Lehre Herbarts. 1896.

Hayward, F. H. The Student's Herbart. 1902.

Hamilton, Sir W. Discussions on Philosophy. Second ed. London, 1853.

Comte, Auguste. Cours de Philosophie Positive. Five vols. Paris, 1830-42. —Politique Positive. Four vols. Paris, 1851-54.

Caird, Edward. The Social Philosophy of Auguste Comte. Glasgow, 1885.

Levy-Bruhl. The Philosophy of Auguste Comte. English trans. London, 1903.

Whewell, Wm. Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences. London, 1840.

Mill, J. S. A System of Logic. Two vols. London, 1843. —On Liberty. London, 1859. —Utilitarianism. London, 1863. —Examination of Sir William Hamilton's Philosophy. London, 1865.

Whittaker, T. "Comte and Mill," in Philosophies Ancient and Modern. London, 1908.

Spencer, Herbert. First Principles. London, 1862. —Essays. Three vols. London, 1891. —Autobiography. London, 1904.

Macpherson, Hector. Herbert Spencer. London, 1900.

Green, T. H. Prolegomena to Ethics. Oxford, 1884.

Green, T. H. Works. Three vols. London, 1885-1900.

Bradley, F. H. Appearance and Reality. Third ed. London, 1889.

Lotze, H. Mikrocosmus. 1856-64. —System der Philosophie. 1874-79. – English trans. of the Microc. Two vols. Edinburgh, 1885. – Of the Metaphysics. Two vols. Oxford. 1884.

Jones, Sir Henry. The Philosophy of Lotze. Glasgow, 1895.

Hartmann, Ed. von. Die Philosophie des Unbewussten. 1869. English trans. by W. C. Coupland. Three vols. London, 1884.

Nietzsche, Fr. Werke. Leipzig, 1895 ff. English trans. in fourteen vols. Edinburgh. (T. N. Foulis.) – D. Halévy, La Vie de Nietzsche. Paris, 1909.

Russell, Bertrand. The Problems of Philosophy (Home University Library). London, 1912.